Looming
How to Run Discworld Noir

The Aesthetic Flaws of Games

Orbital EquationsMovies, books, and other narrative artworks have a well-established critical lexicon; while critics might not agree about any given example, they largely concur on how criticism of these forms should proceed. But what are the ways that a game can manifest aesthetic flaws, and how does this relate to classical art forms?

My basis for this enquiry are the three Rules of Game Worlds that I discussed in my blog-letter to Dan Cook last year. These were intended to be guidelines for creating game worlds – that is, principles for how the fictional world of a game (where its narratives will be set) connect with its mathematical systems (where its mechanics operate). However, I sense that these rules may have some formal depth to them, and indeed might have more general forms that could include other artworks. For now, let us accept them as descriptive ‘rules’, so they can guide an investigation into how games produce aesthetic flaws of kinds that other artworks simply do not.

The three Rules of Game Worlds are as follows:

  1. Setting and mechanics must accord.
  2. Any and all mechanical sub-worlds must merge with the game world.
  3. No-one plays alone.

Each of these can be used to reveal a specific kind of aesthetic flaw unique to games – and indeed, can reveal a schism between different aesthetic values for play that lead to different kinds of aesthetic flaw. This is key to what follows, for we must appreciate that ‘aesthetic flaw’ is not an absolute claim, nor is it ‘merely subjective’: an aesthetic flaw occurs between a game and its player as a direct result of a difference in values.

Ruptures

The first kind of flaw that can occur in the aesthetics of play is the one that has produced the most heat and least light in discussions of games. It is intimately tied up with the First Rule, that ‘setting and mechanics must accord’, or as I might equivalently say, in line with Jesper Juul, that the fiction and the rules must accord. Why does this constitute a rule?

The crucial point to understand is that the rules of a game, its mechanics and systems, are representations of a very particular kind – namely mathematical representations. This is important to appreciate, because we do not often acknowledge that numbers and formulae are at heart representative, despite this being well-established in broad strokes. The number 'three' is a representation of cardinality: every collection of three objects, like the three rules of game worlds, is thus represented by the number three. Similarly, the bell curve ‘shape’ we depict by graphing the Gaussian function of (say) two six-sided dice represents the distribution of results from such a roll. It is precisely because mathematics can and must represent that the sciences that deploy equations (such as physics) are able to derive formulae that represent phenomena like gravity and electrical flow.

But of course, every game is also a representation in the same way that other artworks are: using Kendall Walton’s terms, they are sensory depictions, like paintings, sculpture, and music, or narrations, like books, poetry and radio plays, or hybrids of the two, such as television, comics, and films. This is precisely where the trouble starts! Because whenever there are multiple forms of representation working together, there is the possibility of different aesthetic values about those kinds of representations clashing. This is precisely the problem at the root of the old narratology vs. ludology skirmish, and in contemporary fights over what is confusingly termed ‘formalism’ but which seems broadly equivalent to what is usually called ludology or ludocentrism or some other ludo-prefixed neologism.

A rupture occurs when a player is experiencing a game in one aesthetic mode, but their imaginary experience is interrupted by an intrusion in another mode – and there are two common examples. The first occurs for any player whose aesthetic values have formed around the mathematical representations of a game (broadly, the ludology position). Such players resent the inclusion of animated film clips (cut scenes or cinematics) in games since these elements do not form part of their aesthetic experience, per se. They cause a rupture in the mathematically-structured world they are enjoying by ‘forcing’ the player to operate in a narrative mode. Equivalently, a player whose experience was primarily within a depictive or narrative mode will experience a rupture whenever the mechanical system bluntly forces its way into awareness, for instance, by encouraging the player to make a decision with mechanical benefits that does not fit the imaginary world they were playing within.

Note that the same game could produce a rupture in opposing modes for different players, and that what constitutes an aesthetic flaw for someone coming from a ludology-style position could be an aesthetic strength for others: despite the interruption of the mechanical play, Final Fantasy games from VII onwards are enjoyed by many players precisely because of the extensive use of narrative cut scene rewards that heighten the sense of connection to the world for some players but that can rupture the game experience for others.

Inelegance

The second way that games can manifest aesthetic flaws relates to the Second Rule of Game Worlds, that every mechanical ‘sub-world’ must also align with the fictional world of the game. The point here is that for most games there is not simply one mechanical system feeding into the fictional experiences but rather many. As an extreme example, consider Cooking Mama with its disparate, mechanically unrelated cooking mini-games that are still united within a fictional narrative of cooking such-and-such a meal. Similarly, the classic Access Software games Beach Head and Raid Over Moscow, from 1983 and 84 respectively, consist of a linear sequence of self-contained sub-games with only the number of soldiers remaining carrying on from one stage to another. The component games do merge with a common fictional world - but this once-popular structure tends to feel uncomfortably clanky by contemporary standards.

Inelegance is perceived by players preferring the mathematical mode as a direct consequence of any discontinuity between sub-worlds, including but not restricted to the kind of examples already mentioned. When the systems themselves are the elements of primary importance to creating the fictional world of play, elegance is experienced if the core mechanics conspire to effortlessly deliver that world, to produce more from less. Many strategy games are afforded this praise, although the original Super Mario Bros. is an interesting example of elegance that does not primarily rest upon decision making. A design can be said to ‘lack elegance’, which is to say, expressive simplicity, whenever contrary conditions hold, which to be honest is the norm and not the exception in contemporary games.

Inelegance is thus the awareness of tension in the mechanical supports to a fictional game world, a sense that the pieces do not fit together like well-oiled cogs. There does not appear to be an equivalent problem for those experiencing a game in a narrative or depictive mode, although the excess of unrelated mechanics characterising inelegance is likely to cause a rupture in such a case, and inelegance may be experienced along with the rupture if the player has sufficient appreciation for mechanics.

Perplexity

The final kind of aesthetic flaw I want to draw attention to here is of a slightly different nature, and relates to the Third Rule: no-one plays alone. The essence of this rule is that an artefactual reading of games, treating them as isolated objects, is an incomplete reading of a game, because every game that has ever been made, or ever will be made, is situated in a network of player practices that prepare the player for that experience. The clearest example is with the first person shooter, the control scheme for which is so ingrained among the majority of contemporary players that games using a modified form of this scheme can generate aesthetic displeasure. This is what I am calling perplexity, the experience of re-learning what has already been learned differently, or learning under conditions of insufficient information e.g. a bad tutorial.

It is perhaps worth recognizing that many of the mathematical aesthetic persuasion are also lovers of puzzle-solving, the enjoyment of which occurs within the imagined world and not to any significant degree in the mechanics. The classic text adventure was enjoyed by many of the same players who enjoy complex strategy games. Such players will enjoy picking up a game and learning to play it without instruction because they possess what I term confusion endurance (see "Empirical Game Aesthetics", in the IEEE Handbook of Digital Games). However, such experiences are not what I am calling perplexity, and neither is being stuck on a puzzle usually an example of perplexity (unless the player knows what to do, but cannot comprehend how the game expects them to implement the required action).

Perplexity occurs because two sets of player practices – those of the player, and those of the game’s creators – have collided instead of aligning. The most typical example occurs when the people who make the game insufficiently address the monumental problem of teaching others to play (which is also the pragmatic reason that most mainstream videogames have very similar control schemes). An interesting case is Metroid Prime, which has a control scheme utterly different from other first person shooting games. Players who give up while learning the new scheme have experienced perplexity in my sense; those that master the practice required by this control scheme, on the other hand, are likely to appreciate its uniqueness.

Conclusion

These three aesthetic flaws – rupture, inelegance, and perplexity – are by no means a complete list of the ways in which a game and a player could be aesthetically misaligned. However, they serve to illustrate why certain arguments about games operate unproductively because they proceed from different aesthetic presumptions – typically a focus on the mathematical systems of the game, versus a focus upon the depictive or narrative aspects of its fictional world. There is no coherent argument for claiming superiority or even 'home field advantage' to these modes, because games operate uniquely from other media whichever aesthetic mode we consider. I hope this brief enquiry will provide some illumination on a subject that too often lapses into dogma, and illustrate once again the core principle of all my work in games, whether as researcher, philosopher, or game designer: play is a diverse activity, and its aesthetic appreciation can never be entirely collapsed into simple master principles.

Do you have anecdotes illustrating these aesthetic flaws from your own play with specific games? I’d love to hear about your thoughts and experiences in the comments.

Comments

Feed You can follow this conversation by subscribing to the comment feed for this post.

I found it funny that you outlined three simple master principles and then disclaimed master principles at the end. :) (just teasing gently here -- this is a good piece!).

I think your principles do have clear antecedents: the former is what people avoid calling ludonarrative dissonance these days because the term has fallen out of favor for some reason. The third is covered at length in Theory of Fun as the notion of "noise." I kind of love the term perplexity for it. I've always struggled to convey ythe very important notion you do here, that every individual has their own "window" over the landscape, driven by their past experiences, their cognitive library, their developmental stage, and much more; and that therefore the threshold of perplexity varies radically by individual.

I disagree that there's no comparable notion of elegance from the narrative angle. Dangling plot threads, confusing symbols, and other writerly issues have long been discussed in writing programs using terms like "inelegant." Succint conveyance of depth is highly prized in many forms of poetry. In my talk "Playing with 'Game'" I offered up the example of the short story attributed to Hemingway, about never worn baby shoes.

Lovely essay.

I often think of perplexity in similar terms. The player's activated mental schema (usually triggered by affordances, theming, and other initial stimuli) don't match what the game requires.

Zach Gage had an interesting talk (http://stfj.net/DesigningForProblem-Solvers/) on routine vs non-routine problem solving. Perplexity tends to emerge when a player's expected routine problem solving approach fails to produce incremental expected results.

There's an economic aspect to all this. The 'cost' (in time, effort, stress and confusion) to a player to learn something new is high. Selecting an existing, well trained schema is a common low cost tactic for engaging with a new activity. If that fails, not only is there confusion. There is also the sub-conscious economic choice that perhaps this activity isn't worth spending more effort on. Such economic decision points often carry a large emotional payload. (One reason we love talking about the Prisoner's Dilemma is not just because of the math...the emotions of betrayal and loyalty form a 2x2 soap opera)

There is corollary to this that I see in the MMO space. When the player has a well practiced skill and then the game changes due to an update, all hell breaks loose. Not only does the confusion and the 'is it worth it' emotion kick in, but you've also got a large dose of lose aversion. On top of that since these changes were made by a high power individual (dev) and impact a low power individual (player), any social negotiation that takes place tends towards violent protest; the last refuge of the weak.

(You can also analyze 'elegance' from the player's economic perspective by using the cost of learning)

Thank you both for your comments and support!

Raph: you're absolutely right, I totally missed this by being focussed on mechanical inelegance, but of course there certainly are forms of narrative inelegance, and depictive inelegance, that are parallel cases. If this content gets used elsewhere, I will definitely revise it with this in mind. Thanks for making the point!

Dan: "2x2 soap opera" is the best description of the Prisoner's Dilemma ever. :D And trust you to turn to an economic explanation... clearly, this does apply to these situations, although I wouldn't rush into seeing it in such terms. I worry about the validity of economic explanations because I'm rather sceptical of reasoning about people as-if they were rational, given the general status of humanity as only a potentially rational species, if you see what I mean. But this doesn't undercut anything you say, it just explains why I'm nervous about economic explanations. :)

Seeing elegance as an economic cost is also extremely-you; I think I shall stick to understanding it as an aesthetic experience, whilst acknowledging the alternatives. ;)

All the best to you both!

Chris.

(Reply via http://gamestori.es/2015/02/aesthetics-as-basis-for-conflict-between-players/)

Dear Chris Bateman,

Thank you for your post on the "The Aesthetic Flaws of Games". I am writing to provide an exploratory response to the persistent conflict you refer to, noting that this was not the point of your article.

In your first point about Aesthetic Ruptures, you explain how narrative and mechanical aesthetic modes can lead to player alienation because of their unskillful use. I agree with you, and believe that it is this very difference in aesthetic modes that is the reason why the conflict you refer to exists. You speak more to this in one of your earlier posts, 'The Thin Play of Dear Esther".

I have learned through our past discussions on Twitter of your intention to reduce the sectarianism we see in games, particularly the conflict between the narrative vs mechanical tribes, which can be distracting and destructive. As you wisely told me, be careful of trying to own the term 'Game'. But I am concerned that in seeking a 'perennial philosophy' of games we do a disservice to some of the evolutionary traits that games have developed.

While narrative and mechanics are co-joined and influence each other, the fact that an improperly used mode can jar a player's experience leads me to conclude these are different game accords. Yes, they are both forms of representation (one of mathematics and outcomes and one of narrative and meaning) but sharing that trait does not make them the same. In the same way all things are made up of atoms, not everything is atomic in the same way as demonstrated by the Periodic Table's diversity. I think that games have distinct qualities that cut across mechanics, narrative, and genre, and could be used shed light on the issue.

Allow me to use the analogy of game aesthetic modes as being like a playground that has different structures of play. Instead of us telling others to play nice in the same sandbox, since it is all sand after all, I am saying that we must expand our perspective. Instead we should go beyond the sandbox and build a decent fence that clearly delineates the different play structures, since a sandbox is only one kind of play. We don't want our sandbox builders to be disturbed by the monkey bar climbers.

It is this focus that has become the basis of my Gamestori.es theory. That is: It is players that bring to the game their aesthetic wants, and they take from the game the lessons and stories that they in turn tell to others. You have called these different wants aesthetic modes, but I call them Immersion Accords. I see a total of eight accords, of which I will mention two to not distract from this reply's focus. The first accord is that of Pretend and second is that of Performance.

Pretend is about the Player taking on a role, everything from a Tetris block controller, to a imagined avatar in Zork, to a graphical representation of a space marine in Doom. The invitation to Pretend is no different than the children games that we all grew playing as the magic and charm is not lost on us as adults! In Pretending games help us explore artistic and humanistic aspects, a simulation of being depressed, a stranger walking in a strange land, a cloud, etc. Players are in a position to experience a new perspective and to pretend to be something they are not.

When a game is solely focused on Pretend, then it intentionally leaves out other accords, particularly that of Performance. Performance is where games are about challenging the player. What fascinates me is the irony of games generally being considered frivolous yet can require immense effort and work to succeed at them. A game where Performance is required, expects its player to sweat, to lose, and to win. Yes, they can also Pretend to be a WWII Paratrooper, but the Pretending is intentionally superficial as the game's emphasis is based around action and skill.

The traditional criticism from the Pretend fans-tribe is that these action games reinforce immaturity, with their trope focus on power fantasies. The response from the Performance fans-tribe is that their games are real games since you need to actually develop skills to win at them. And on it goes. The effort to invalidate the opposing group because they don't play the same way is asinine. I have you to thank for helping me see the light in this regard.

Tribal social transgressions aside, I think that the two play areas are well formed and we would all do better to accept it. As you have said, diversity of play is natural, so this would lead to a play ecosystem. While a playground can have sandboxes and a monkey bar sets (and so much more), it is beneficial to create fences between the play structures to keep players happy. A welcoming gate in the fence can allow players to go from play experience to play experience as they wish.

Good fences make good neighbors as Robert Frost was told. It is my hope that through Gamestori.es I can help establish these neighborly fences and gates, so that the diversity of play can have the tools needed to provide a supportive ecosystem.

With best regards,

Chris Billows

Verify your Comment

Previewing your Comment

This is only a preview. Your comment has not yet been posted.

Working...
Your comment could not be posted. Error type:
Your comment has been posted. Post another comment

The letters and numbers you entered did not match the image. Please try again.

As a final step before posting your comment, enter the letters and numbers you see in the image below. This prevents automated programs from posting comments.

Having trouble reading this image? View an alternate.

Working...

Post a comment

Your Information

(Name is required. Email address will not be displayed with the comment.)