BrainHex Succeeds Beyond Expectations
Friends of ihobo

Towards Videogame Aesthetics II: Unit Operations

ian_bogost What resources are currently available for developing videogame criticism or aesthetics? Although rather thin on the ground, there is not a complete vacuum, and one useful contribution can be found in the principles of unit operations.

In 2006, Ian Bogost published Unit Operations: An Approach to Videogame Criticism, in which he develops a critical theory suitable for application to any medium – including (but not limited to) poetry, literature, cinema or digital games. The book has a reputation for being difficult – Bogost himself has remarked: "It is a hard book, and I am aware that some readers may not be prepared for it. But it's a hard topic... and I tried not to candy coat that challenge." How difficult any particular reader finds the book will depend upon their background: anyone who is unfamiliar with art criticism in general, who has no experience with philosophy, or who has little experience with computer science will easily become lost. But really, this isn't the biggest problem most people with an interest in videogames will face tackling the book; I suspect the biggest issue is that most people who are into videogames just do not care about the kind of criticism Bogost's book addresses.

An example will serve to illustrate. In a crucial chapter of the book, Bogost draws a line of connection between Charles Baudelaire's poem "À une passante" (1860), Charles Bukowski's poem "A woman on the street" (1996), Jean-Pierre Jeunet's film Amélie (2001) and Wil Wright' game The Sims: Hot Date (Maxis, 2001). He traces the connections between these artworks in terms of the theme of 'chance encounters', and the significance these hold for urban life, a phenomenon that has become established and then intensified over the same period of time as these source materials span. It's a masterful piece of literary criticism, able to take the principles of conventional literary theory and show how they can be applied to very different cultural artefacts. That it concludes on a videogame is Bogost's masterstroke – because by the time he reaches this part of his discussion his theme is already perfectly well established, and the move into digital media feels like a short step not a hop or a jump. The effortless of this thread underline's Bogost's core point – that videogames are just as suitable for cultural analysis as anything else.

To get to the point of being able to make comparisons such as this, Bogost builds a wide scaffold on a number of different foundations, such as Heidegger's Gestell ('enframing'), Spinoza's universal substance, Leibnitz's monads and especially Alain Badiou's ontology of sets, which in turn builds on the work of the mathematician Georg Cantor. A quick introduction to these philosophical concepts is provided in the early parts of the book, although anyone coming to them for the first time via Bogost is likely to be left dangling. It is the studious scholarship of Bogost's work which ironically acts as a barrier to selling his approach to a wider audience – it's not necessary to understand the foundations to live in this particular house. But Bogost's project is expressly about how that house came to be built, and it is only in reference to this framework that he discusses how to live in that house at all. This makes Bogost's unit operations a very hard sell to anyone who isn't coming from an academic background.

The 'unit operations' of the title refer to process steps – in fact, this is what the term means in chemical and industrial engineering (a point that might have argued against using it in this specific context). Bogost asserts that "any medium... can be read as a configurative system, an arrangement of discrete, interlocking units of expressive meaning." He calls the general instances of procedural expression unit operations, but also notes in passing at one point that they corresponds to literary critic Walter Benjamin's term motif – figures and tropes assembled into a framework or rule set. Bogost explicitly asserts the identity between Benjamin's motif and his own unit operation, and speaking for myself I found his book far easier to read when I opted to substitute "motif" for "unit operation" about half the times it appeared whilst still bearing in mind Bogost's intended terminology.

A unit operation, in the context of the system of cultural criticism sketched in this book, is thus a minimal component of meaning (or a "mode of meaning-making"), one which prefers to focus on discrete, disconnected actions over more deterministic or progressive systems. Part of Bogost's core argument rests on the claim that there are gains to be made in shifting away from a focus on system operations and towards unit operations, while recognising that "neither strategy is permanently detached from the other." This tension was never fully resolved for me – while I could see the thrust of Bogost's argument, I found it hard not to see unit operations itself as a form of system. But then, Bogost shows he is aware of this pressure, which likely cannot be entirely resolved.

One of the more interesting implications Bogost draws out of his approach is an analysis of the effect of simulation on personal subjectivity. Following media theorist Sherry Turkle, a compelling argument is developed that there is no possibility of a simulation that does not possess an ideology: "The objective simulation is a myth because games cannot help but carry the baggage of ideology." Turkle notes that when facing a particular simulation we can either buy into its assumptions (simulation resignation) or we can reject them (simulation denial), and Bogost develops this into what he calls (following a similar term from Derrida) "simulation fever", or perhaps more clearly, "simulation anxiety". A key opening in the possibilities for game criticism is opened in this space.

Simulation anxiety is a "nervous discomfort" caused by the disjunction between a game's model of real world situations and our interpretation of that model. Since what is being represented is often something we have our own ideas and opinions about, the gaps between these two models is the site of the tension that can lead to resignation or denial. Bogost convincingly argues that his idea of 'simulation fever' demonstrates that games allow us to "expose and explore complicated human conditions", and as such reading them purely as tools for entertainment is to radically underestimate the medium. I certainly agree with this claim.

However, there is a severe limit to Bogost's approach: it is guided by the principles of modern literary theory, and as such any aesthetic elements of his approach are limited to "aesthetic meaning", which is precisely what Bogost admits his approach to comparative videogame criticism is aiming at. But meaning, and the discussion of meanings, is far from the central focus of aesthetics. In fact, while future game critics will need to be able to discuss the meaning and context of games as cultural artefacts – a situation facilitated by Bogost's significant achievements in Unit Operations – this is almost entirely tangential to the pressing need I have claimed for game aesthetics. Such future critics may well make use of a unit operational perspective (or at the very least some similar mechanism for cross-cultural analysis) but without an aesthetic theory we will not have secured the case for games as artworks. We will simply have accepted them as one set of cultural artefacts amongst many.

Next week: Against Interpretation

Comments

Feed You can follow this conversation by subscribing to the comment feed for this post.

"nervous discomfort"? "simulation fever"?

Am I mistaken or do we see a new class of "therapeutic terms" enter the arena of the Game ;-))???

As mentioned previously I approach these issues preferably from the perspective of systemic psychology and psychotherapy the "Internal Family Systems Model" by R..C. Schwartz would be a good "game-like" - actually even role-play like - starting point.

Also, I can't help but mention - since you brought up this issue of ontologies so prominently - that Bateson and Spencer-Brwon to me would be the places to look for a ontology to start from - in addition these are somewhat compatible with Wittgenstein and Walton as a bonus ;-). Best wishes!

Actually, come to think of it I wonder if BrainHex could not qualify as a model for the aesthetic experience in game play?!
Is there a detailed explanation out there about the Neuro-science used? And some details of the constructs applied? If I had to answer what the kind of experience the Test questions are asking for "aesthetic" would be my answer;)
This discussion certainly warrants a closer look, don't you think? Best!

This chain of reasoning would then of course mean that BrainHex could be interpreted (and extended) as a Form of "Internal Players Systems Model" founded not only in neuropsychological inspired analogies (if I got that right?) but also neuropsychological inspired therapeutic practice (flavors and siblings - I mentioned Schwartz just as a prominent english speaking protagonist - of the mentioned approach can claim quite some success in various therapeutic fields not just family therapy). Best!

translucy: thanks for your comments! I corrected the Somerset error and deleted your note concerning it.

Bateson is someone I've been skirting - he's on my reading list, but the new stuff coming in just keeps pushing him back farther and farther! I never intended to get sucked into aesthetics and philosophy of art, but now that I have I have so much reading to do it's really pushed me back on my philosophy of mind...

Regarding BrainHex as aesthetic - yes, I think there is an aesthetic of play inherent to the model here. But it's incomplete - it doesn't directly address representational aesthetic issues, and I suspect what we need going forward is something that can take both functional and representational aesthetic issues in its stride. I'm continuing the research. :)

As for 'therapeutic terms' - hey, this is all from Bogost. I didn't do it. :)

Best wishes!

Looking at BrainHex I am not unconvinced
that a "representational" approach to aesthetics is so necessary let alone valuable as you seem to suggest.
In fact, my reaction to Sontag's caveat against Ober- interpretation is to focus on the reflexive and experiential
possibilities in the critique of art rarely explored.

In that sense the experience of taking the BrainHex Test in combination with a conscious use of video gaming could do more and may be has already done more for your cause than you think.

Why not intensify the practice of aesthetics rather than the Theory of representation, e.g. through an Arts project combining BrainHex and dedicated Video Gaming in the Arts context of a
museum (as a reframing of context away from the ever
suspicious online world) . Ars Electronica could be a venue for such a project. The result could get pretty close to the experience of "Spieltrieb" the way Schiller envisioned it 200 years ago ;-). Best!

translucy: let me briefly make the case that representational aspects are important to game aesthetics.

A complete theory of game aesthetics must be able to respond to the aesthetic experiences that games create in people. These aesthetic experiences depend upon more than just the emotions of play - they depend upon the representational elements as well.

So, for instance, the aesthetic experience of Pac-man is different to the aesthetic experience of Fac-man, an obvious Pac-man rip off. The emotions of play in both cases are identical, but there is something to the experience of Pac-man that is more than the emotions of play - a representational element. (A parallel can be made here to arguments about the difference between an experience of an old master, and a forgery of that old master, but this is a sideline!)

I'm certainly not denying that in many respects BrainHex points towards a functional aesthetics of play. But I believe that a complete theory of game aesthetics must allow representational elements their place. And as I argued in Slaying the First Colossus, it is not so easy to set the representation aside when it comes to considering the emotions of play!

Best wishes!

Thank you, the additional link on your thoughts behind "representation" as part of the concept helps a lot! I do agree that your approach is consistent. Yet, from a perspective mainly based in consulting practice it is hard to place too much emphasis on "representation" as a central part. In consulting one can observe that the reflexion of representation is a fluid and private matter similar to the use of language. Of course, there are large areas which should be considered as "authorised" but if these areas are also central to aesthetics remains to be seen (see the interesting comments on "Authorised stories") Looking forward to more on this!

Thanks translucy! Obviously, I'm still working out the kinks in my approach, but I'm convinced we cannot simply put representation aside in game aesthetics - but the full argument for this will have to wait. :)

All the best!

Verify your Comment

Previewing your Comment

This is only a preview. Your comment has not yet been posted.

Working...
Your comment could not be posted. Error type:
Your comment has been posted. Post another comment

The letters and numbers you entered did not match the image. Please try again.

As a final step before posting your comment, enter the letters and numbers you see in the image below. This prevents automated programs from posting comments.

Having trouble reading this image? View an alternate.

Working...

Post a comment

Your Information

(Name is required. Email address will not be displayed with the comment.)